This text has somehow broken formulas layout. Some mathematical symbols both from standard math notation and my notations are substituted by other symbols hindering understanding of this text. Navigation is inconvenient. Ads disturb to read. Bibliography is missing. Purchase high quality PDF or paper book to read this conveniently.
Abstract. I rigorously consider (generalized) limit of an arbitrary (discontinuous) function, defined in terms of funcoids [?] (funcoids are briefly considered in this work, for people unfamiliar with them). Definition of generalized limit makes it obvious to define such things as derivative of an arbitrary function, integral of an arbitrary function, sum of arbitrary series, etc. It is given a definition of non-differentiable solution of a (partial) differential equation. It’s raised the question how do such solutions “look like” starting a possible big future research program.
This helps you to calculate series, derivatives, integrals without first checking that they exist. This theory allows you to check this once in the end of the calculation, instead of checking several times in the middle.
The generalized derivatives and integrals are linear operators. For example is defined and true for every function.
Welcome to an easy way of non-smooth analysis for all kinds of functions. Now things not defined before, like derivative of Dirichlet function, are defined and are easy to use in practical engineering calculations.
This has an advantage over (“competing” with my theory) distributions theory based analysis, that for example any two functions in my analysis are multiplicible, while in distributions analysis you need to check a complex condition before multiplying two functions. This is a straigthforward, “no cost” advantage over traditional ways of non-smooth analysis. Moreover, in distributions analysis not every function has a derivative, but in my analysis every function is differentiable. The advantages are further bettered by the fact that I consider (generalized) limits of any values, not for a limited class of functions.
The generalized solution of one simple example differential equation is also considered.
For continuous and differentiable functions, my analysis, of course, gives the same results as the traditional analysis.
2010 Mathematics Subject Classification. 54J05, 54A05, 54D99, 54E05, 54E17, 54E99
Key words and phrases. nonsmooth analysis, non-smooth analysis, algebraic general topology, limit, funcoid, differential equations
I defined funcoid and based on this generalized limit of an arbitrary (even discontinuous) function in [?].
In this article I consider generalized limits in more details.
This article is written in such a way that a reader could understand the main ideas on generalized limits without resorting to reading [?] beforehand, but to follow the proofs you need read that first.
Definition of generalized limit makes it obvious to define such things as derivative of an arbitrary function, integral of an arbitrary function, etc.
Note that generalized limit is a “composite” object, not just a simple real number, point, or “regular” vector.
For an example, consider some real function from -axis to -axis:
Take it’s infinitely small fragment (in our example, an infinitely small interval for around zero; see below for an explanation what is infinitely small):
Next consider that with a value replaced with an infinitely small interval like :
Now we have “an infinitely thin and short strip”. In fact, it is the same as an “infinitely small rectangle” (Why? So infinitely small behave, it can be counter-intuitive, but if we consider the above meditations formally, we could get this result):
This infinitely small rectangle’s position uniquely characterizes the limit of our function (in our example at ).
If we consider the set of all rectangles we obtain by shifting this rectangle by adding an arbitrary number to , we get
Such sets one-to-one corresponds to the value of the limit of our function (at ): Knowing such the set, we can calculate the limit (take its arbitrary element and get its so to say -limit point) and knowing the limit value ( ), we could write down the definition of this set.
So we have a formula for generalized limit:
where is the group of all horizontal shifts of our space , is the function of which we are taking limit restricted to the infinitely small interval around the point , is “stretching” our function graph into the infinitely thin “strip” by applying a topological operation to it.
What all this (especially “infinitely small”) means? It is filters and “funcoids” (see below for the definition).
Why we consider all shifts of our infinitely small rectangle? To make the limit not dependent of the point to which tends. Otherwise the limit would depend on the point .
Note that for discontinuous functions elements of our set (our limit is a set) won’t be infinitely small “rectangles” (as on the pictures), but would “touch” more than just one value.
The interesting thing here is that we can apply the above formula to every function: for example to a discontinuous function, Dirichlet function, unbounded function, unbounded and discontinuous at every point function, etc. In short, the generalized limit is defined for every function. We have a definition of limit for every function, not only a continuous function!
And it works not only for real numbers. It would work for example for any function between two topological vector spaces (a vector space with a topology).
Hurrah! Now we can define derivative and integral of every function.
We will denote partial orders as , the join as , and the meet as . I denote the greatest element of an order as and the least as .
I will denote the set of filters as .
Intuitively, filters may be like infinitely small sets: Consider the filter whose elements are subsets of containing every neighborhood of zero.
I will call the principal filter corresponding to set the filter
I will order filters reversely to set theoretic inclusion:
It is easy to prove that filters on a set form a lattice. For filters , :
In [?] we also prove that the set of filters is an atomic (and moreover atomistic) lattice. We will denote atoms (traditionally called maximal filters) under a filter as .
Moreover, filters form a complete lattice. For a set of filters:
I will reprise (without proofs, that you are able to easily fill in by yourself) several equivalent definitions of funcoid from [?]:
Binary relation between two sets (source and destination of the funcoid), conforming to the axioms:
Pair of functions between the sets of filters filters on some two sets (source and destination of the funcoid), conforming to the formula:
A function from the set of subsets of some set (source of the funcoid) to the set of filters on some set (destination of the funcoid), conforming to the axioms:
Note that we define things to have the equations:
I will call endofuncoid a funcoid whose source and destination are the same.
Funcoids form a semigroup (or precategory, dependently on the exact axioms) with the operation defined by the formula:
We denote and .
Funcoids also form a poset which is a complete lattice (see [?]), with the order
Also funcoids are a generalization of binary relations. I will denote the funcoid corresponding to a binary relation as , the defining formulas are
Funcoids are a generalization of topological spaces. For every topological space it can be constructed a funcoid:
or its reverse
It is easy to check that the above is a funcoid.
Funcoids are an obvious a generalization of proximity spaces (see [?]).
Restricted identity funcoid generalizes an indentity function:
Restricting a funcoid to a filter is . (This generalizes restricting a function to a set.)
In [?] we also have a funcoid called funcoidal product (generalizing Cartesian product of two sets) of two filters and is defined as:
It’s easy to check that this is really a funcoid.
Also, , for a funcoid .
The following is a straigthforward generalization of the well known concepts of adherent point of a set (more generally a cluster point of a filter), a limit point of a filter, and limit of a function in a topological space.
Note 4. Due to an unfortunate choice of terminology, limit point of a filter is not a generalization of a limit point of a set. Limit point for a set isn’t a beautiful term and we won’t use it (in this work), so by limit point we will always mean a limit point of a filter.
So, generalizing the corresponding concepts for topological spaces:
Let be a funcoid.
Definition 5. I will denote lattice operations as and , the least and the greatest elements as and correspondingly.
Proposition 8. There exists a (unique) funcoid such that is exactly the set of adherent points of for every argument set , provided that is a principal filter.
Proof. Obvious. □
Proposition 10. If is reflexive, then there exists a (unique) “dual funcoid” (a pointfree funcoid, see [?]) such that is exactly the set of limit points of for every argument set .
Proof. The set of limit points of the empty set is the maximal set.
The set of limit points of (for sets , ) is the set of points such that that is and that is the intersection of the set of limit points of and .
Thus the set of limit points is a component of such a pointfree funcoid. □
Proof. Because for an ultrafilter . □
We have shown that concepts of both limit points and adherent points are essentially funcoids. In traditional general topology limit of a function is defined using limit points of a filter. We will generalize it to limit regarding an arbitrary funcoid (in place of the funcoid describing limit points). We will call this arbitrary funcoid the point funcoid and denote it .
Remark 14. If , then the limit is either an one-element or the empty set (“no limit” in traditional topology).
In [?] limit for a funcoid was defined this way: tends to filter ( ) regarding a funcoid on a filter iff
is such a point that tends to .
Proof. In this proof will mean our definition, not the definition from [?]. We need to prove that .
Really,
A funcoid is -separable iff for every and . A funcoid is Hausdorff ( -separable) iff is -separable.
If is Hausdorff ( -separable) (see [?]), then there exists no more than one .
Let be a (fixed) funcoid. For example, where is some proximity or or (up to a duality).
By definion (for every funcoid ).
Remark 17. If is an limit point (considered as an one-element set) of and is a function, then the above defined is the same as limit in traditional calculus and topology (except that it is an one-element set of points instead of a point). Empty set means “no limit”.
Let some group (e.g. the group of all shifts on a vector space, to give an example) is fixed.
Definition 18. Axiomatic generalized limit is a two-arguments function from the set to the set of functions defined on filters such that exists such that by the formula:
Proposition 20. To describe an axiomatic generalized limit, it’s enough to define it on ultrafilters.
Proof. Easily follows from the fact [?] that a funcoid is described by its values on ultrafilters. □
Thus axiomatic generalized limit gives a detailed behavior of a function at a filter (its limit at every its atomic subfilter).
Proof.
□
Let be an arbitrary point of the space . Consider the constant function whose value is this . Then the first axiom above determines the for every filter .
I will denote .
In other words, on Hausdorff topologies the set of singularities with non-empty domains is an extension of the set of points (up to a bijection).
In [?] generalized limit is defined like the formula:
|
(1) |
We suppose:
Let and be endofuncoids (on sets , ). Let be a transitive permutation group on .
We require that and every commute, that is
|
(2) |
We require for every
|
(3) |
Proposition 26. Formula (3 ) follows from .
Proof. Let . Then
(Here is the identity element of the semigroup of endofuncoids.) □
So we have (generalized) limits of arbitrary functions acting from to . (The functions in consideration are not required to be continuous.)
Remark 27. Most typically is the group of translations of some topological vector space1 . So in particular we have defined limit of an arbitrary function acting from a vector topological space to a topological space.
The function will define an injection from the set of points of the space (“numbers”, “points”, or “vectors”) to the set of all (generalized) limits (i.e. values which may take).
Proof.
Reversely
where is the identify element of .□
Proof.
□Corollary 31. The defined in this section for generalized limits “coincides” with the defined in the section about axiomatic generalized limits.
In further we will use one of the definitions of continuity from [?]:
Proof. ; thus ; consequently we have
;
So .
Thus
□
Remark 33. Without the requirement of the last theorem would not work in the case of removable singularity.
Proof. ; ;
On the other hand,
So .
□
We have injective if for every distinct that is if is -separable.
Definition 38. Hausdorff funcoid is such a funcoid that every proper filter on its image has at most one limit.
Proof.
If 2 does not hold, then there exist distinct points and such that . So and are both limit points of , and thus is not Hausdorff.
Suppose is proper.
Remark 41. It is enough to be “almost entirely defined” (having nonempty value everywhere except of one point).
Obvious 42. For a complete funcoid induced by a topological space this coincides with the traditional definition of a Hausdorff topological space.
I will call singularities the set of generalized limits of the form where is an entirely defined funcoid and ranges all points of .
I will call axiomatic singularities the set of axiomatic generalized limits of the form where is an entirely defined funcoid and ranges all points of .
Switching back and forth between generalized limits and what I call -singularities:
Proposition 43. Let the funcoid is Kolmogorov and is entirely defined. Then is an injection from the set of singularities to the set of monovalued functions.
Proof. That it’s an injection is obvious.
We need to prove that for each such that . Really, for , . We have . Similarly for some . Thus because otherwise and so ,
contradiction.
It remains to prove that conforms to the axioms.
The second axiom is obvious.
It remains to prove that
Really, is equal to an such that . So .
Theorem 44. The following are mutually inverse bijections between generalized limits and axiomatic generalized limits on a filter such that for all :
Proof. First, we need to prove that the mapping from to is monovalued. For it’s obvious. It’s enough to show that if and . But for it follows from the fact that for as directly follow from theorem conditions.
Next we need to show that our functions are mutually inverse.
Let be a generalized limit. Let be the axiomatic generalized limit corresponding to it by 1 . Let be the generalized limit corresponding to it by 2 . Then
for some . That is, if then for some and if for some then . So .
Let now be an axiomatic generalized limit. Let be the generalized limit corresponding to it by by 2 . Let be the axiomatic generalized limit corresponding to it by 1 . Then maps to whenever that is whenever
and and it undefined if there is no such . In other words, maps to if (the case “otherwise” is not to be considered because ). So . □
So if we define a function on the set of functions whose values are funcoids, we automatically define (as this injection preimage) a function on the set of singularities. Let’s do it.
Let be a (possibly multivalued) multiargument function.
As usually in calculus:
Let is an arbitrary multiargument function.
Definition 45. for an indexed (by ) family of functions of the same domain to domains of arguments of .
This is an advanced section requiring studying reloids and pointfree funcoids from [?].
Proof. Need to prove (theorem 1650 in [?])
Really,
But by theorem 1875 in [?]:
So, . Thus follows the thesis. □
Proof. As composition of two components of pointfree funcoids:
.
Note that is a component of a pointfree funcoid because
□
Proof. Consider values on principal atomic filters. □
Definition 53. Define applying finitary (multivalued) functions to and indexed family of axiomatic generalized limits of the same domain (and probably different destination sets) as
(Here is considered as a function on filters, is considered as a function on indexed famililies of functions.)
Proof. because is reflexive.
for some funcoid .
.
□
Proposition 55. The conditions of the previous propositions hold for and for if they hold for . More exactly:
Let is transitive ( ) and reflexive. Then:
Proof. 1 . Reflexivity is obvious. Prove that . Really, where is the “core part”. 2 . Reflexivity is obvious. Prove that . Really,
□
Definition 56. Applying to singularities: (applicable only if limits are taken on filters that are equal up to for ).
Proof. We will prove instead
Equivalently transforming:
;
;
Obviously, .
Reversely, applying continuity times, we get:
So . □
Proof. The first equality follows from the above.
It remains to prove
Equivalently transforming,
;
□
Theorem 59. Let be a filter on . Let be the set of all functions such that . Let , be finitary multiargument functions on . Let be an index set. Let , . Then
implies
provided that and are continuous regarding in each argument.
Remark 60. This theorem implies that if is a group, ring, vector space, etc., then is also accordingly a group, ring, vector space, etc.
Proof. Every for some function .
By proved above,
It’s enough to prove
But that’s trivial. □
Conjecture 61. The above theorem stays true if is instead a set of limits of monovalued funcoids2 .
Having generalized limit, we can in an obvious way define derivative of an arbitrary function.
We can also define definite integral of an arbitrary function (I remind that integral is just a limit on a certain filter). The result may differ dependently on whether we use Riemann and Lebesgue integrals.
From above it follows that my generalized derivatives and integrals are linear operators.
Proposition 62. Axiomatic generalized limits of monovalued funcoids for and coincide on ultrafilers.
Proof. Follow from the facts that the image of an ultrafilter by an atomic funcoid is an ultrafilter and that and coincide on ultrafilters. □
Question 63. Under which conditions the algebras of all functions on the set of of all possible values of axiomatic generalized limits between two fixed sets and induced (as described above) by functions for generalized limits are pairwise isomorphic (with an obvious bijection) for:
Moreover, if is -separable, they are also isomorphic to the case (remark: for a pretopology , it’s the proximity of two sets being near if they have intersecting closures). The isomorphism is composing every element of a value of an axiomatic generalized limit with on the left ( ).
Also let question how to generalize the above for functions between different kinds of singularities is also not yet settled.
Above we have defined (having fixed endofuncoids and ) for every set of “points” its set of singularities .
We can further consider
etc.
If we try to put our generalized derivative into say the differential equation on real numbers, we have a trouble: The left part belongs to the set of functions to and the right part to the set of functions to , where is the set of solutions. How to equate them? If would be just we would take the left part of the type and equate them using the injection defined above. But stop, it does not work: if the left part is of then the right part, too. So the left part would be , etc. infinitely.
So we need to consider the entire set (supersingularities)
But what is the limit (and derivative) on this set? And how to perform addition, subtraction, multiplication, division, etc. on this set?
Finitary functions on the set are easy: just apply to arguments belonging to “lower” parts of the hierarchy of singularities a finite number of times, to make them to belong to the same singularity level (the biggest singularity level of all arguments).
Instead of generalized limit, we will use “regular” limit but on the set (which below we will make into a funcoid) rather than on the set .
See? We have a definition of (finite) differential equations (even partial differential equations) for discontinuous functions. It is just a differential equation on the ring (if is a ring).
What nondifferentiable solutions of such equations do look like? No idea! Do they contain singularities of higher levels of the above hierarchy? What about singularities in our sense at the center of a blackhole (that contain “lost” information)? We have something intriguing to research.
I remind that for funcoid the relation can be thought as generalized nearness.
We will extend from the set of points to the set of funcoids from a (fixed) set to having the same domain (or empty domain):
where is the set of ultrafilters over the filter .
The above makes a pointfree funcoid (as defined in [?]) on this set of funcoids:
Proof. Because funcoids are isomorphic to filters on certain boolean lattice, it’s enough to prove:
The first two formulas are obvious. Let’s prove the third (the fourth is similar):
□
We will define two singularities being “near” in terms of -singularities (that are essentially the same as singularities):
Two -singularities , are near iff there exist two elements of and correspondingly such that and every , are near.
Let’s prove it defines a funcoid on the set of -singularities:
Proof. Not and not are obvious.
It remains to prove for example
but that’s obvious. □
It remains to define the funcoid of supersingularities.
Let , be sets of supersingularities.
We will define and to be near iff there exist natural , such that
Let’s prove that the above formula really defines a funcoid:
Proof. We need to show
The first two formulas are obvious. Let’s prove the third (the fourth is similar):
□
We will denote .
Proof.
The case remains as an exercise to the reader. □
Proof.
More generally,
Definition 68. Let be a function from a real vector space to a real vector space . Let moreover function space be conforming to conditions for generalized limit that is have a funcoid such as
Then Porton derivative
It obviously generalizes to every (left or right) module over a division ring, where the ring has a funcoid and a group whose elements are commuting with.
Compare to Gateaux derivative [?]:
We see that Gateaux derivative is a special case of Porton derivative. Fréchet derivative, in turn, is special case of Gateaux derivative: “If is Fréchet differentiable, then it is also Gateaux differentiable, and its Fréchet and Gateaux derivatives agree.” [?]
It is well known ([?]) that Gateaux derivative may produce a non-linear dependency on , so Porton derivative, too, may be non-linear in .
TODO: It can be generalized for spaces without (but with subtraction)?
Therefore, as is a linear function of we can write where and .
Proof.
□
Definition 73. Let be a funcoid from the object of an endofuncoid to a poset. A funcoid has local minimum at point when
Replace in the last formula by a filter . Equivalently transforming, .
If is an ultrafilers, it further is equivalent to ; ; .
If we take as the definition of having local minimum on a filter , then it has a local minimum on a filter iff it has local minimum on each atom of .
We can also fully analogous define strict local minimum replacing by .
Obvious 75. If a function from a normed space to funcoid (with all conditions for axiomatic generalized limit definition of the derivative) has local minimum at point , then
(here is considered as an axiomatic generalized limit).
Note that arbitrary pseudocontinuous continuations of generalized solutions of differential equations (diffeqs) are silly:
Let is a diffeq and let the equality is undefined at some point (e.g. contains division by zero). Let be its solution with derivative . Replace the value in undefined point of the solution by an arbitrary value and calculate the derivative at this point. No need to hold at this point because the point is outside of the domain of the original solution. Then replace in our solution the value at this point by and the derivative by . Then we have another continuation of the solution because the equality holds both for the point and all other points.
Thus, we can take any solution and add one point of it with an arbitrary value. That’s largely a nonsense from the practical point of view. (Why we would arbitrarily change one point of the solution?)
So I will require for generalized solutions instead that the derivative is pseudocontinuous.
Next, we will consider a particular example, the diffeq . Let us find its continuations of generalized solutions to the entire real line (including ) with a being pseudocontinuous.
As it’s well known, its solutions in the traditional sense are for and for where , are arbitrary constants. The derivative is .
Remark 77. We could consider solutions on the space of supersingularities and it would be the same, except that we would be allowed to take , arbitrary supersingularities instead of real numbers. This is because the supersingularities form a ring and thus the algorithm of solving the diffeq is the same as for the real numbers, thus producing the solutions of the same form.
Let’s find the pseudocontinuous generalized derivative at zero by pseudocontinuity:
On the other hand, by the definition of derivative
The equality is possible only when .
So, finally, our solution is for and .
A thing to notice that now the solution is “whole”: it exists at zero and does not split to two “branches” with independent constants. Our is a real function, but the derivative has a singularity in my sense.
We considered generalized solutions with pseudocontinuous derivative. It is apparently the right way to define a class of generalized solutions. Now I will consider also several apparently wrong classes of solutions.
Let us try to require the solution of our diffeq to be pseudocontinuous instead of its derivative to be pseudocontinuous.
We already have the solution for nonzero points. For zero:
So the derivative:
The equality is impossible.
This is a conjecture about general relativity in context of quantum gravity. If the conjecture is true and you prove it, you have serious chances to share Nobel prize with me.
Consider generalized (as per the “Generalized limit” course) solutions of Einstein equations with the requirement that they are pseudodifferentiable in timelike curves.
In spacelike curves they may be not differentiable.
I will call this theory supersingular GR.
By the analogy with equation in the previous chapter, when it was solved without pseudodifferentiability requirement I conjecture that singularities may take arbitrary values. I further conjecture that these singularities may hold information about formation of a black hole, solving the black hole information paradox in another way than Hawking radiation.
The produces theory does not conform to observations: In my QG the space is the same for all quantum worlds. (I consider many-world interpretation a proved theory because of [?].) Therefore gravity is the same in worlds with different positions of the Sun, what is obviously wrong.
It seems my theory can be improved to become compatible with the many world-interpretation:
This text has somehow broken formulas layout. Some mathematical symbols both from standard math notation and my notations are substituted by other symbols hindering understanding of this text. Navigation is inconvenient. Ads disturb to read. Bibliography is missing. Purchase high quality PDF or paper book to read this conveniently.